[Search for users] [Overall Top Noters] [List of all Conferences] [Download this site]

Conference rusure::math

Title:Mathematics at DEC
Moderator:RUSURE::EDP
Created:Mon Feb 03 1986
Last Modified:Fri Jun 06 1997
Last Successful Update:Fri Jun 06 1997
Number of topics:2083
Total number of notes:14613

339.0. "Tiling" by RANI::LEICHTERJ () Sun Oct 06 1985 03:18

Suppose you are given a infinite supply of tiles, but of only a finite number
of distinct varieties.  The tiles are to be placed on the plane; each has a
fixed orientation, and cannot be rotated or turned over.  (A reflected or
rotated tile is considered to be a distinct tile.  You may have been given the
same tile in one or more rotated versions, but you have to work with what you
have been given.)

It is known to be possible, using the tiles you have been given, to tile the
upper right hand quadrant of the plane.  Show it is possible to tile the entire
plane.

							-- Jerry
Hint:

What does this have to do with note 335?
T.RTitleUserPersonal
Name
DateLines
339.1BEING::POSTPISCHILMon Oct 07 1985 13:337
I saw this problem already, when I looked up the infinity lemma.  Isn't there
more to the tiles than you describe?  I believe Knuth uses square tiles, with
numbers on each of the sides, and the numbers are required to match those
of adjacent tiles.


				-- edp
339.2TAV02::NITSANThu Oct 10 1985 03:1610
Aha... tiles again...

I didn't follow the infinite discussion on 335 closely, but if you can tile
the "upper right corner" of the plane ( that is {(x,y)|x,y>=0} ), then you
can tile "bigger" corners ( e.g. {(x,y)|x,y>=-1} ) by a 1:1 transformation
of the previous "tiling". Now you have a sequence (with 0,-1,-2,...) of
"upper right corners" each containing the previous, each perfectly tiled.
can you use 335 now ?

Nitsan
339.3METOO::YARBROUGHThu Oct 10 1985 16:2014
That argument doesn't work, because each such transformation leaves the same
problem that you had before - you still have an unlimited space to cover.
What you need is an argument that shows how one can append an L-shaped
area while leaving the rest intact. That will provide a sound basis for an
induction argument.

Your approach reminds me of the argument that all girls have blue eyes:
assume it's true for N<k, then consider the k+1st girl in combination with
any (k-1) subset of the rest. That forms a set of k girls, which by the
hypothesis all have blue eyes, so the k+1st girl must have blue eyes. The
solution to this riddle is to stare into the eyes of a number of girls
until you get tired of the exercise...

Lynn Yarbrough
339.41-d caseHERON::BUCHANANcombinatorial bomb squadFri Sep 14 1990 08:2620
	Let's solve the one-dimensional case, which at least gets us
over the hurdle of considering infinity properly.

	Suppose we can tile the positive x-axis, can we tile the whole
x-axis?

	The key thing is that there's only a finite number of different
possible tiles.   Each of them will have a lhs and a rhs drawn from a
(necessarily finite) set A.   We can view each possible tile as an edge
in a directed graph G with vertex set A:

	edge e links a to a' IFF a is the lhs of e and a' is the rhs of e.

	Now, we know that there is a vertex s in G such that there is
an infinite path in G starting from s.   Since |A| is finite, this means
that there is a cycle in G.   Using this cycle and no other tiles, we can
trivially tile the x-axis.

Regards,
Andrew.
339.5use the infinity lemmaTRACE::GILBERTOwnership ObligatesFri Sep 14 1990 20:4428
339.6Clap, Reply & Next QuestionHERON::BUCHANANcombinatorial bomb squadMon Sep 17 1990 09:2434
>For the tiling problem, ... "The set of all solutions to the problem of tiling
>squares with an even number of cells on each side forms an oriented tree, if the
>sons of each 2nx2n solution x are the possible (2n+2)x(2n+2) solutions that can
>be obtained by bordering x. ..."  This was observed by Hao Wang in the Nov 1965
>issue of "Scientific American".

Neat!

>Frankly, I don't quite understand why Wang resorted to so bushy a tree; the
>tree formed by larger and larger tilings of the upper right plane should also
>meet the requisites for application of the infinity lemma.  Wang's proof *does*
>hide any possible concerns regarding the "boundary" (along the x- and y-axes).

You need to have a rooted tree.   Sure, there are an infinite number of tilings
of the upper right plane, but if you pick any one of them, then you can only
extend it by a finite number of descendants from it, before you stop.

>And then there's Kruskal's theorem, which runs counter to the infinity lemma.

What's that?

	Question (for which I haven't looked for the answer):
	With one dimension, we know that if we can tile the naturals, then
there is a *periodic* tiling of the integers.   With two dimensions, we know
that if we can tile the upper right plane, we can tile the whole plane.   But
can we exhibit a set of tiles for which the only tilings of the plane are 
non-periodic?

	Penrose tiling is inadmissible here because we require each tile to
be square.   However a similar proof to the proof of non-periodicity for the
Penrose tiling is what I would look for first...

Regards,
Andrew.
339.7TRACE::GILBERTOwnership ObligatesMon Sep 17 1990 18:1321
>> why Wang resorted to so bushy a tree
>You need to have a rooted tree.   Sure, there are an infinite number of tilings
>of the upper right plane, but if you pick any one of them, then you can only
>extend it by a finite number of descendants from it, before you stop.

Suppose you can tile the upper right plane.  Let T(xa..xb,ya..yb) represent the
(xb-xa+1)x(yb-ya+1) tiling that starts at position (xa,xb).  Let T(0..0,0..0)
be the root of the tree; T(0..1,0..1) is its son, and in general, T(0..n,0..n)
has son T(0..n+1,0..n+1).  Why doesn't this tree fit the requirements of the
infinity lemma?

>Kruskal's theorem.  What's that?

See the reference in Knuth.

>But can we exhibit a set of tiles for which the only tilings of the plane are
>non-periodic?

Yes.  See the reference in Knuth.  One of the exercises gives 92 domino types
having nothing but non-periodic (nontoroidal) tilings of the plane.  The answer
mentions a similar set of only 35 domino types.
339.8confusedHERON::BUCHANANcombinatorial bomb squadTue Sep 18 1990 08:1924
>Suppose you can tile the upper right plane.  Let T(xa..xb,ya..yb) represent the
>(xb-xa+1)x(yb-ya+1) tiling that starts at position (xa,xb).  Let T(0..0,0..0)
>be the root of the tree; T(0..1,0..1) is its son, and in general, T(0..n,0..n)
>has son T(0..n+1,0..n+1).  Why doesn't this tree fit the requirements of the
>infinity lemma?

	The tree as you define it here will certainly satisfy the infinity
lemma precondition and postcondition.   However...

	If that is how you are defining 'son' then all that you can do with it
is prove that you can tile the upper right plane!

	I fear I haven't followed what you were trying to say.   If you think 
it's worth it, then please clarify what your construction is and how it differs
from the existing solution.

>Yes.  See the reference in Knuth.  One of the exercises gives 92 domino types
>having nothing but non-periodic (nontoroidal) tilings of the plane.  The answer
>mentions a similar set of only 35 domino types.

	I must look it up some time.   35 seems a lot.

Regards,
Andrew.
339.9TRACE::GILBERTOwnership ObligatesWed Sep 19 1990 16:559
>	If that is how you are defining 'son' then all that you can do with it
> is prove that you can tile the upper right plane!
>	I fear I haven't followed what you were trying to say.

Ayup; you've understood.  Now my confusion is this:  Why does Wang's tree
prove something more than just tiling an upper right plane?

Both trees satisfy the requirements of the infinity lemma in the same way.
The same result should pop out the other end, n'est pas? right?
339.10GUESS::DERAMODan D'EramoWed Sep 19 1990 17:1616
>> Ayup; you've understood.  Now my confusion is this:  Why does Wang's tree
>> prove something more than just tiling an upper right plane?
>>
>> Both trees satisfy the requirements of the infinity lemma in the same way.
>> The same result should pop out the other end, n'est pas? right?

	If you follow one of the infinite paths that exists through
	one tree, you have a nested series of tilings the nth level
	of which covers, say, the square [-n,n] x [-,n].  The union
	of the levels covers the entire plane.  If you follow one of
	the infinite paths that exists through the other tree, however,
	you have a nested series of tilings the nth level of which
	covers, say, the square [0,n] x [0,n].  The union of the
	levels covers the upper right quarter plane.

	Dan