T.R | Title | User | Personal Name | Date | Lines |
---|
846.1 | Can I use Euclid's Fifth Postulate? | POOL::HALLYB | You have the right to remain silent. | Tue Mar 29 1988 21:55 | 2 |
| > Back to basics on this one: using the Pythagorean Thm. or any branch of
> math that rests on it (analytic geometry, trig, etc.) begs the question.
|
846.2 | Maybe that's what makes it an interesting problem. | ZFC::DERAMO | Reunite Gondwanaland! | Tue Mar 29 1988 23:30 | 8 |
| Re .-1: Can I use Euclid's Fifth Postulate?
Does Euclid's Fifth Postulate necessarily follow from the existence
of a triangle with sides a,b,c such that a^2 + b^2 = c^2?
Hint: I don't know the answer to this.
Dan
|
846.3 | | CHOVAX::YOUNG | Dumb, Expensive, Dumb ... (Pick Two) | Wed Mar 30 1988 04:23 | 2 |
| I am pretty sure that the Parallel Postulate, being a postulate,
is not derived from Pythagoras' theorem.
|
846.4 | | ZFC::DERAMO | Reunite Gondwanaland! | Wed Mar 30 1988 16:08 | 12 |
| The Parallel Postulate is "equivalent" to such statements as
- the sum of the angles of a triangle is 180 degrees
- there exist similar but non-congruent triangles
- [I think] there exist triangles of arbitrarily large area
Many of the early "proofs" of the Parallel Postulate used one of
these other statements. What I was asking was if the existence
of an "a^2 + b^2 = c^2" triangle was yet another equivalent to
the above.
Dan
|
846.5 | Hmmm. | AKQJ10::YARBROUGH | Why is computing so labor intensive? | Wed Mar 30 1988 17:38 | 3 |
| I don't recall seeing any proof of PyThm. that makes any reference to the
Parallel Postulate. Maybe it's buried in some intermediate constructions,
e.g. of a square with given side, or something.
|
846.6 | | CLT::GILBERT | | Wed Mar 30 1988 17:47 | 25 |
| Using "the sum of the angles of a triangle is 180 degrees" with
the following diagram, we see that the center is a square. Letting
the inner square have side c, we see that (a+b)^2 = 2ab + c^2, so
that a^2 + b^2 = c^2, proving the Pythagorean Theorem.
b a
+-------+----+
| / \ |
a | / \ | b
| / \ |
+ \|
|\ +
| \ / |
b | \ / | a
| \ / |
+----+-------+
a b
Now to prove te reverse. Suppose we have a triangle with sides
a, b, and c, such that a^2 + b^2 = c^2, but the angle opposite c
is not a right angle. Construct a triangle with sides a and b,
with a right angle between those sides. Then the third side must
equal c (by the Pythagorean Theorem, above), and so it is similar
to the first triangle. Hence (by the law of similarity of triangles?),
the first triangle must also have a right angle opposite side c.
|
846.7 | So much for soft sarcasm | POOL::HALLYB | You have the right to remain silent. | Wed Mar 30 1988 18:49 | 41 |
| Re: .2, .4
The Pythagorean theorem is equivalent to the parallel postulate.
In the classic non-Euclidean geometries, the analogues to the
Pythagorean Theorem are a^2 + b^2 > c^2 and a^2 + b^2 < c^2 .
Hence to prove the converse you do in fact need the 5th postulate
or one of its many equivalents.
I think a proof of .0 not using the PthM (as .6 did) could be
constructed by starting out with
P
+
|\
| \ c P, R, and S are points,
b | \ a, b, and c are lengths
| \
+----+
R a S
and constructing point Q so that PR || SQ and SQ is of length b.
P Q
+ +
|\ |
| \ c| P, Q, R, and S are points,
b | \ | b a, b, and c are lengths
| \|
+----+
R a S
Therefore RQ (not drawn) = PS = c, since RQ^2 = a^2 + b^2
Therefore triangle PRS is congruent to triangles RSQ, SQP, and QPR
(by Side-Side-Side), hence all four angles of PQRS are equal. Since
the angles of a quadrilateral sum to 4 right angles and all are
equal, well you get the idea...
John
|
846.8 | still seems to violate the restriction in .0 | ZFC::DERAMO | My karma ran over my dogma. | Wed Mar 30 1988 23:03 | 10 |
| It seems to me that both .6 and .7 are assuming the Pyth. Thm.
to start. Why do you say (in .7) RQ^2 = a^2 + b^2. Also, assuming
that the angles of a quadrilateral sum to 4 right angles means
assuming that the angles of a triangle sum to 2 right angles (draw
a diagonal), which is the same as assuming the Pythagorean Theorem.
Shouldn't it be possible to prove this, instead of assuming it,
given a triangle with sides a,b,c such that a^ + b^2 = c^2.
Dan
|
846.9 | oops | ZFC::DERAMO | Reunite Gondwanaland! | Thu Mar 31 1988 02:03 | 7 |
846.10 | Back to the drawing board, straightedge, and compass | POOL::HALLYB | You have the right to remain silent. | Thu Mar 31 1988 02:17 | 12 |
| .8> ... Why do you say (in .7) RQ^2 = a^2 + b^2. ...
Oops, you're right. We are given that a^2 + b^2 = c^2, but haven't
established that PRS is congruent to RSQ, so at that point in the
proof can't assume that angle R is the same as S, which is what
you need to sail thru the rest.
But you will have to "take the fifth" (nice phrase) sooner or later.
I thought it was rather cute to use the 5th right at the start where
SQ is constructed parallel to PR.
John
|
846.11 | Chinese discovery? | COMICS::DEMORGAN | Richard De Morgan, UK CSC/CS | Thu Mar 31 1988 06:55 | 5 |
| Re .6: I think I read somewhere that this proof of Pyth Thm was
discovered by the Chinese some 1000 years before Pythagoras. Anybody
know of any evidence of this? I wish I'd come across this proof
before I did my 'O' level maths - I could never remember the usual
proof for more than a few days.
|
846.12 | Non Euclidean geometries | ZFC::DERAMO | Take my advice, I'm not using it | Thu Mar 31 1988 15:29 | 12 |
| Any proof as a reply here that states "construct the parallel to ..."
should be met with a loud
"WHICH PARALLEL???"
or a
"BUT THERE AREN'T ANY!!!"
(-:
Dan
|
846.13 | Gilbert's proof fine, it does *not* use Pythagorean thm | VIDEO::OSMAN | type video::user$7:[osman]eric.vt240 | Thu Mar 31 1988 19:44 | 10 |
| I'd like to defend Gilbert's proof in .6. He did *not* use the
Pythagorean theorem, he first proved it. For those that persist and
say "yeah, but then he used it, right?", merely redo .6 and
call it something other than Pythagorean. After all, anything you
prove along the way you can name anything you want.
The only thing I might ask for in .6 is that the "sum of angles
of triangle equals 180" might need proof.
/Eric
|
846.14 | Can we be more direct? | AKQJ10::YARBROUGH | Why is computing so labor intensive? | Thu Mar 31 1988 20:32 | 16 |
| I agree with .-1; what I was seeking is a direct constructive proof, much
like the one Gilbert cited, but without putting the bucket of water on the
floor.
In case my reference was cryptic, there is the following old chestnut:
Problem 1:
Given: a bucket of water on the floor, and a stove with burner lighted;
to boil the water.
Solution: pick up the bucket of water and put it on top of the burner.
Problem 2:
Given: a bucket of water on a table, and a stove with burner lighted;
to boil the water.
Solution: pick up the bucket of water and put it on the floor. See problem 1.
|
846.15 | | CLT::GILBERT | | Thu Mar 31 1988 21:34 | 3 |
| One part of .6 was a hand-wave. That is, if the corresponding sides
of two triangles are equal, then the corresponding angles are equal.
Does this also depend on the parallel postulate?
|
846.16 | You have my word on it. (-: Isuzu theorem! | ZFC::DERAMO | Take my advice, I'm not using it | Fri Apr 01 1988 00:05 | 9 |
| Re .15
>> One part of .6 was a hand-wave. That is, if the corresponding sides
>> of two triangles are equal, then the corresponding angles are equal.
>> Does this also depend on the parallel postulate?
I am sure that it doesn't.
Dan
|
846.17 | | CHALK::HALLYB | You have the right to remain silent. | Fri Apr 01 1988 13:55 | 18 |
| >> One part of .6 was a hand-wave. That is, if the corresponding sides
>> of two triangles are equal, then the corresponding angles are equal.
>> Does this also depend on the parallel postulate?
. P
. .
Q . . R If you draw a kite and construct
. . the chord QR, you then have two
. . triangles QPR and QSR that share
. . side QR. Since QR = QR does it
. . then follow that angle P = angle S?
. S
You've got to have more restrictions than listed above, and depend
on stronger theorems, some if not all of which are equivalent to
the parallel postulate.
John
|
846.18 | a non-Euclidean counter-example | ZFC::DERAMO | Take my advice, I'm not using it | Fri Apr 01 1988 14:00 | 15 |
| Aha. I have finally convinced myself that some form of the
parallel postulate is needed for this proof. Consider a triangle
on the surface of a sphere. Put one vertex at the north pole, the
other two on the equator a quarter circumference apart. This triangle
will have three right angles. Now let a and b be the "longitudinal"
sides, from the north pole to the equator. Side c will be the edge
that runs along the equator. Increase the length of side c by
increasing the angle at the north pole between sides a and b. You
can increase the length of side c until c^2 = a^2 + b^2 = 2 a^2 = 2 b^2.
This triangle will not have a right angle opposite side c.
So, all objections about proofs using something equivalent to the
parallel postulate are withdrawn. It is needed here.
Dan
|
846.19 | all the sides? | ZFC::DERAMO | Take my advice, I'm not using it | Fri Apr 01 1988 14:04 | 14 |
| Re .6, .17
>> >> One part of .6 was a hand-wave. That is, if the corresponding sides
>> >> of two triangles are equal, then the corresponding angles are equal.
>> >> Does this also depend on the parallel postulate?
>>
>> You've got to have more restrictions than listed above,
I took "corresponding sides of two triangles are equal" to mean
all three sides in turn are equal. Your example uses only one of the
three sides. I haven't re-examined .6 yet to see which he meant,
though.
Dan
|
846.20 | congruent and similar triangles | PULSAR::WALLY | Wally Neilsen-Steinhardt | Fri Apr 08 1988 16:56 | 16 |
| Yes, solving the problem in .0 will require the fifth postulate.
The pythagorean theorem is not necessarily true in non-euclidean
geometries.
And yes, that is equivalent to saying that the sum of angles in
a triangle is equal to two right angles.
And it is equivalent to saying that if all three sides of two triangles
are proportional then the corresponding angles are equal.
But it is not equivalent to the statement that if all three
corresponding sides of two triangles are equal, then the corresponding
angles are also equal. This is true in Euclidean geometry and the two
non-euclidean geometries I know about. I seem to remember proving
that in my youth, before we started using the fifth postulate, but
that was long ago.
|
846.21 | I wish I could remember more of this stuff. | ZFC::DERAMO | Daniel V. D'Eramo | Fri Apr 08 1988 23:04 | 24 |
| Re .-1
I am also sure that I have heard that it requires Euclidean geometry
(i.e., the parallel postulate) to prove that there can be "similar
triangles" that are not "congruent".
Now what do the words I quoted mean?
similar = the same angles?
similar = proportional sides?
similar = the same angles and proportional sides?
congruent = the same sides?
congruent = the same sides and the same angles?
Do any of these possible definitions imply a later one on the list?
Anyway, in non-Euclidean geometries I think the area of a triangle is
a function of the difference between the sum of its angles and 180
degrees. So if you "scale" the triangle, changing the sides but all
by the same factor, the resulting "proportional" triangle has a
different area and so a different sum of angles.
Dan
|
846.22 | | CADM::ROTH | If you plant ice you'll harvest wind | Mon Apr 11 1988 15:52 | 13 |
| You cannot define what an 'angle' is without first defining a metric.
So in a sense, .0 takes the modern view of geometry, where the Pythagorean
theorem (defining the euclidean metric) is reduced to a postulate, and
then the ramifications of it are deduced. The advantages seem to be
that it generalizes naturally to arbitrary differentiable manifolds and
lets one define 'intrinsic' properties of them without the clumsy
requirement of imbedding them in another space. The first example
of this was Gauss' studies of surfaces (I believe this is the case.)
This intrinsic-ness of space was philosophically very important for the
development of the theory of relativity...
- Jim
|
846.23 | | COOKIE::WAHL | Dave Wahl: Database Systems AD, CX01-2/N22 | Tue Apr 12 1988 02:30 | 19 |
| Congruence and similarity I remember; the rest I need to think about a
bit. Euclid said that two triangles are similar if their sides are in
proportion. Two triangles are congruent if a one-to-one coorespondence
can be constructed between their vertices such that corresponding sides
are congruent and corresponding angles are congruent. Congruence of line
segments and angles were accepted by Euclid as "common notions".
The line segment congruence axiom says, informally that you can always "move"
one line segment onto a ray and mark off a second line segment congruent to
the first. The congruent angle axiom similarly says you can "lay off" a
congruent angle on a line segment from an existing angle.
The last congruence axioms is the old side-angle-side axiom for congruent
triangles.
I believe it is the Sacheri (Saccheri?)-Legendre theorem which shows
that the best you can do without the parallel postulate is to say that
the sum of the angles in a triangle is <= 2 right triangles. You need
the parallel postulate to prove that the sum = 2 right triangles.
|
846.24 | similar, non-congruent triangles exist | PULSAR::WALLY | Wally Neilsen-Steinhardt | Tue Apr 12 1988 16:35 | 25 |
| re: < Note 846.21 by ZFC::DERAMO "Daniel V. D'Eramo" >
-< I wish I could remember more of this stuff. >-
> I am also sure that I have heard that it requires Euclidean geometry
> (i.e., the parallel postulate) to prove that there can be "similar
> triangles" that are not "congruent".
Yes, this is my favorite statement of the fifth postulate: similar,
non-congruent triangles exist.
> similar = the same angles?
> similar = proportional sides?
> similar = the same angles and proportional sides?
Yes, in Euclidean geometry all these are equivalent. I believe
that the second statement defines similar, and the fifth postulate
is used to prove the first.
> congruent = the same sides?
> congruent = the same sides and the same angles?
As I remember it, the second statement is the definition of congruent,
and the first four postulates (and probably a few things taken for
granted) are used to show that the first is equivalent, that is,
equal sides imply equal angles.
|
846.25 | the two right angles | PULSAR::WALLY | Wally Neilsen-Steinhardt | Tue Apr 12 1988 16:42 | 13 |
| re: < Note 846.23 by COOKIE::WAHL "Dave Wahl: Database Systems AD, CX01-2/N22" >
> I believe it is the Sacheri (Saccheri?)-Legendre theorem which shows
> that the best you can do without the parallel postulate is to say that
> the sum of the angles in a triangle is <= 2 right triangles.
This theorem must refer to a special case. On the surface of a
sphere, the sum of angles in a triangle > 2 right angles.
> You need
> the parallel postulate to prove that the sum = 2 right triangles.
the parallel postulate or one of its many equivalents
|
846.26 | Two different non-Euclidean gemoetries | POOL::HALLYB | You have the right to remain silent. | Tue Apr 12 1988 17:36 | 11 |
| >> I believe it is the Sacheri (Saccheri?)-Legendre theorem which shows
>> that the best you can do without the parallel postulate is to say that
>> the sum of the angles in a triangle is <= 2 right triangles.
>
> This theorem must refer to a special case. On the surface of a
> sphere, the sum of angles in a triangle > 2 right angles.
The Saccheri stuff holds in hyperbolic geometry, i.e., more than
one nonintersecting line. The reverse is true in elliptic geometry,
i.e, two lines always intersect iff the sum of angles in a triangle
is greater than 2 right angles.
|